Atheist
In A Foxhole
How a
committed atheist confronted with death might find
consolation.
By David
Rönnegard
March 08, 2016
"Information
Clearing House"
- I am a secularly-minded philosopher. Faith
is not a virtue I hold. In particular, I disbelieve
claims to knowledge about God’s existence or will.
As an atheist and a Humanist, my approach to life
has been grounded on rational thought and empirical
evidence. I consider death to be the end of our
conscious existence, and that any meaning that life
may have resides with man.
Public
reflecting on life is often done in fear of, but
seldom in the face of, death. I am in the privileged
but unenviable position of doing the latter. I have
just been told, at the age of 37, that I have stage
four lung cancer. Atheism and news of one’s
impending death would appear to be a particularly
unfortunate combination. From where does a faithless
philosopher obtain consolation? What provides
meaning for a life lived, and acceptance of a fate
anticipated?
Having
never had an inclination towards the supernatural,
religion has never appeared to me as either credible
or a source of comfort. News of looming death has
not encouraged me to grasp for false consolation,
though consolation is sorely needed. Rather, my
obsession with death has hitherto been soothed by
Socrates’ description of philosophy as the process
by which one comes to accept one’s own death. Now,
confronted with the terminal nature of life at a
young age, I wonder if I have sufficiently moved
along this process of acceptance, which is
invariably a very personal one.
Philosophers are often caricatured as dealing with
the big questions, particularly the meaning
of life, but I have rarely observed this to be a
matter of concern among professional philosophers,
other than fleetingly in conversation with
colleagues after some beers. Few thinkers of a
non-religious bent have tried to address the
question of meaning head-on. Perhaps as independent
thinkers philosophers nowadays have a tacit
understanding that life’s meaning or value is a
personal journey; but most philosophers I know
don’t seem to spend much time pondering the meaning
of their own lives either. And if the philosophers
among us are not doing it, who is? It’s the elephant
in the room of secular thought.
Having been
schooled in the analytic philosophical tradition I
don’t find myself laden with a rich history of
thought on life’s meaning. Until recently it has
been remarkably absent in the analytic literature,
and recent contributions have centered on unpacking
‘the meaning of life’: that is, most efforts have
been made to understand the meaning of ‘meaning’, as
well as getting a better grip of the term ‘life’.
Bertrand Russell’s words that “everything is vague
to a degree you do not realize till you have tried
to make it precise” convey the analytic tradition’s
admirable ambition for clarity. But frankly, none of
this is very helpful to the individual struggling
with mortality in search of meaning. It is both too
abstract to be comprehensible to the uninitiated,
and too divorced of sentiment to be of personal
guidance. The Existential tradition of continental
philosophy proves more insightful: Existentialism
emphasizes the subjective nature of being; that is,
the essence of what it is like to be us. It gets us
closer to considering what it is we value, which is
central to shaping a meaningful life for ourselves
as we pursue those values. That said, for the
Existentialist, ‘meaning’ (and thus also ‘the
meaning of life’), is primarily a descriptive rather
than prescriptive notion.
Biting The Bullet
In this
void, religion has largely claimed a contemplative
monopoly on the prescriptive meaning of life and
death. Here meaning is provided by the creed, often
with the ultimate promise of escaping death
altogether. (For example, John 11:25: “he that
believeth in me, though he were dead, yet shall he
live.”) The human desire for religion is partly
founded on our fear of death and its consolation
through faith in a hereafter.
However,
the comforting notion of an afterlife is
astonishingly unlikely to be true, and it is not
needed. I don’t think that death should be feared,
because looked squarely in the eye it can be seen to
be the same as the silence from which we came.
Moreover, with no afterlife, we should make more of
the period we now have – a length of time that is
largely unknown to most of us. Therefore our fears
should be either to waste that time or to not be
given enough of it.
A
non-religious outlook does not hold the promise of
immortality, but it does provide some relief. For
example, I have no sense of being unfairly
afflicted. I do not wonder what I have done to
deserve this – and I most certainly do not think
that anyone else is more deserving of it. Well, I
can think of some, but that’s beside the point. The
point is that no one has handed me these cards, and
therefore I do not need to waste emotional capital
pondering the injustice of my lot. I have simply
pulled the short straw in the malignant mutation
lottery.
Religious
people sometimes say that no-one is an atheist in a
foxhole (presumably that applies to cancerburrows
too) – the presumption being that “ye of little
faith” will grasp for solace through a supernatural
belief system hitherto rejected because ye have now
had a change of fortune. But if wishful thinking
were so easy, and effective, I would simply wish the
cancer to be gone – that would seem to be the
straightforward wishful approach. The Humanist
approach, eschewing the supernatural, closes off
this ‘afterlife’ avenue and keeps us grounded in
making the best of the one life we know we do have.
The hitch is that sometimes we don’t get as many
years as we hoped (let alone an afterlife). I wish I
could say something consoling; but perhaps it’s part
of the Humanist’s ontological bullet that one must
at this point bite down hard.
Enduring Sentiments
With
nothing left to lose you are made very aware of what
you never want to lose. You are confronted with life
in a way that only the news of death can bring. My
nurse has a tattoo along her inner forearm that
reads “live life like you will die today, love like
you will live forever.” Living in the present
becomes a much easier prescription to realize when
you know there is less time to be had. The
importance of those we love is also made more acute,
and the relative insignificance of financial matters
is cemented. I have the luxury of saying this partly
because I live in Sweden, where, thanks to universal
healthcare, my very sizable medical bills are of no
consequence. But regardless, money is of limited use
if you cannot spend it. With no materialism to
obstruct the view, our intangible values can be seen
more clearly.
For most
people life appears as a forward projection rather
than a countdown. But both perspectives are needed.
At some point in our lives the horizon will appear
and we must ask ourselves the following question:
looking in the rear-view mirror, how do I feel about
what I leave behind?
The
distinction between ‘objectivist’ and ‘subjectivist’
conceptions of the meaning of life hinges on whether
anything is valuable beyond personal perceptions of
value. Religious outlooks, where value is externally
imposed by a deity, are clearly objectivist, whilst
Humanist outlooks, grounded in the mind of man, tend
toward subjectivism. I don’t think there is anything
valuable beyond the subjective perception of value,
because value is a mental state, which requires a
subject who does the valuing. Nonetheless, there
might be room for sentiments that we all find
valuable. The terminality of life helps us see that
value.
When
regarding life as a forward projection, a life of
self-indulgence doesn’t seem unreasonable, but what
we value in the moment may not seem so important
when seen in the context of a finite life. When
forced to look through a rear-view mirror, the life
of self-indulgence has already been had. What then
remains of value to give the sensation of a life
fully lived? What are the sentiments that endure?
As I see
it, these sentiments are memories we hold dear that
bear the test of time: joy over moments shared with
those we love; perhaps pride over achievements
recognized. It is difficult to put words on such
mental states, but they contain the numinous. It is
said that philosophy takes over where religion ends,
but in this instance poetry might take over where
analytic philosophy ends. Conceptual precision may
need to give way to language more suited to
sentiment.
What gives
rise to enduring sentiments may well vary among us,
but my new shortsighted spectacles suggest to me
that they will spring from events that have touched
the lives of others. When such sentiments are shared
they live on in those who stay behind. And so the
Humanist quest for immortality is not corporeal.
Rather, it takes many forms that touch lives, such
as the friendships we maintain, the children we give
birth to, the enterprises we start, and the books we
write; in essence, the footprints we leave behind.
A life
fully lived is in large part a life lived through
others. While we are alive others provide meaning to
us by being the objects of our affection. When we
are dead we provide meaning to others by continuing
to be the objects of theirs. The awareness of death
highlights such enduring sentiments and shows us
what we value deeply. By implication, faith in an
afterlife, which amounts to a denial of death, may
hinder such insight.
© Dr David
Rönnegard
David
Rönnegard has a PhD in philosophy from the London
School of Economics, and is a researcher and teacher
in corporate social responsibility in Stockholm. |