Moral
Enhancement
By Julian Savulescu and Ingmar Persson
February
01, 2016 "Information
Clearing House"
- "Philosophy
Now" -
For the vast
majority of our 150,000 years or so on the planet,
we lived in small, close-knit groups, working hard
with primitive tools to scratch sufficient food and
shelter from the land. Sometimes we competed with
other small groups for limited resources. Thanks to
evolution, we are supremely well adapted to that
world, not only physically, but psychologically,
socially and through our moral dispositions.
But this is
no longer the world in which we live. The rapid
advances of science and technology have radically
altered our circumstances over just a few centuries.
The population has increased a thousand times since
the agricultural revolution eight thousand years
ago. Human societies consist of millions of people.
Where our ancestors’ tools shaped the few acres on
which they lived, the technologies we use today have
effects across the world, and across time, with the
hangovers of climate change and nuclear disaster
stretching far into the future. The pace of
scientific change is exponential. But has our moral
psychology kept up?
With great
power comes great responsibility. However,
evolutionary pressures have not developed for us a
psychology that enables us to cope with the moral
problems our new power creates. Our political and
economic systems only exacerbate this.
Industrialisation and mechanisation have enabled us
to exploit natural resources so efficiently that we
have over-stressed two-thirds of the most important
eco-systems.
A basic
fact about the human condition is that it is easier
for us to harm each other than to benefit each
other. It is easier for us to kill than it is for us
to save a life; easier to injure than to cure.
Scientific developments have enhanced our capacity
to benefit, but they have enhanced our ability to
harm still further. As a result, our power to harm
is overwhelming. We are capable of forever putting
an end to all higher life on this planet. Our
success in learning to manipulate the world around
us has left us facing two major threats: climate
change – along with the attendant problems
caused by increasingly scarce natural resources –
and war, using immensely powerful weapons.
What is to be done to counter these threats?
Our Natural Moral
Psychology
Our sense
of morality developed around the imbalance between
our capacities to harm and to benefit on the small
scale, in groups the size of a small village or a
nomadic tribe – no bigger than a hundred and fifty
or so people. To take the most basic example, we
naturally feel bad when we cause harm to others
within our social groups. And commonsense morality
links responsibility directly to causation: the more
we feel we caused an outcome, the more we feel
responsible for it. So causing a harm feels worse
than neglecting to create a benefit. The set of
rights that we have developed from this basic rule
includes rights not to be harmed, but not rights to
receive benefits. And we typically extend these
rights only to our small group of family and close
acquaintances. When we lived in small groups, these
rights were sufficient to prevent us harming one
another. But in the age of the global society and of
weapons with global reach, they cannot protect us
well enough.
There are
three other aspects of our evolved psychology which
have similarly emerged from the imbalance between
the ease of harming and the difficulty of
benefiting, and which likewise have been protective
in the past, but leave us open now to unprecedented
risk:
1. Our
vulnerability to harm has left us loss-averse,
preferring to protect against losses than to seek
benefits of a similar level.
2. We
naturally focus on the immediate future, and on our
immediate circle of friends. We discount the distant
future in making judgements, and can only empathise
with a few individuals based on their proximity or
similarity to us, rather than, say, on the basis of
their situations. So our ability to cooperate,
applying our notions of fairness and justice, is
limited to our circle, a small circle of family and
friends. Strangers, or out-group members, in
contrast, are generally mistrusted, their tragedies
downplayed, and their offences magnified.
3. We feel
responsible if we have individually caused a bad
outcome, but less responsible if we are part of a
large group causing the same outcome and our own
actions can’t be singled out.
Case Study: Climate
Change and the Tragedy of the Commons
There is a
well-known cooperation or coordination problem
called ‘the tragedy of the commons’. In its original
terms, it asks whether a group of village herdsmen
sharing common pasture can trust each other to the
extent that it will be rational for each of them to
reduce the grazing of their own cattle when
necessary to prevent over-grazing. One herdsman
alone cannot achieve the necessary saving if the
others continue to over-exploit the resource. If
they simply use up the resource he has saved, he has
lost his own chance to graze but has gained no long
term security, so it is not rational for him to
self-sacrifice. It is rational for an individual to
reduce his own herd’s grazing only if he can trust a
sufficient number of other herdsmen to do the same.
Consequently, if the herdsmen do not trust each
other, most of them will fail to reduce their
grazing, with the result that they will all starve.
The tragedy
of the commons can serve as a simplified small-scale
model of our current environmental problems, which
are caused by billions of polluters, each of whom
contributes some individually-undetectable amount of
carbon dioxide to the atmosphere. Unfortunately, in
such a model, the larger the number of participants
the more inevitable the tragedy, since the larger
the group, the less concern and trust the
participants have for one another. Also, it is
harder to detect free-riders in a larger group, and
humans are prone to free ride, benefiting from the
sacrifice of others while refusing to sacrifice
themselves. Moreover, individual damage is likely to
become imperceptible, preventing effective shaming
mechanisms and reducing individual guilt.
Anthropogenic climate change and environmental
destruction have additional complicating factors.
Although there is a large body of scientific work
showing that the human emission of greenhouse gases
contributes to global climate change, it is still
possible to entertain doubts about the exact scale
of the effects we are causing – for example, whether
our actions will make the global temperature
increase by 2°C or whether it will go higher, even
to 4°C – and how harmful such a climate change will
be.
In
addition, our bias towards the near future leaves us
less able to adequately appreciate the graver
effects of our actions, as they will occur in the
more remote future. The damage we’re responsible for
today will probably not begin to bite until the end
of the present century. We will not benefit from
even drastic action now, and nor will our children.
Similarly, although the affluent countries are
responsible for the greatest emissions, it is in
general destitute countries in the South that will
suffer most from their harmful effects (although
Australia and the south-west of the United States
will also have their fair share of droughts). Our
limited and parochial altruism is not strong enough
to provide a reason for us to give up our
consumerist life-styles for the sake of our distant
descendants, or our distant contemporaries in
far-away places.
Given the
psychological obstacles preventing us from
voluntarily dealing with climate change, effective
changes would need to be enforced by legislation.
However, politicians in democracies are unlikely to
propose such legislation. Effective measures will
need to be tough, and so are unlikely to win a
political leader a second term in office. Can voters
be persuaded to sacrifice their own comfort and
convenience to protect the interests of people who
are not even born yet, or to protect species of
animals they have never even heard of? Will
democracy ever be able to free itself from powerful
industrial interests? Democracy is likely to fail.
Developed countries have the technology and wealth
to deal with climate change, but we do not have the
political will.
If we keep
believing that responsibility is directly linked to
causation, that we are more responsible for the
results of our actions than the results of our
omissions, and that if we share responsibility for
an outcome with others our individual responsibility
is lowered or removed, then we will not be able to
solve modern problems like climate change, where
each person’s actions contribute imperceptibly but
inevitably. If we reject these beliefs, we will see
that we in the rich, developed countries are more
responsible for the misery occurring in destitute,
developing countries than we are spontaneously
inclined to think. But will our attitudes change?
Moral
Bioenhancement
Our moral
shortcomings are preventing our political
institutions from acting effectively. Enhancing our
moral motivation would enable us to act better for
distant people, future generations, and non-human
animals. One method to achieve this enhancement is
already practised in all societies: moral education.
Al Gore, Friends of the Earth and Oxfam have already
had success with campaigns vividly representing the
problems our selfish actions are creating for others
– others around the world and in the future. But
there is another possibility emerging. Our knowledge
of human biology – in particular of genetics and
neurobiology – is beginning to enable us to directly
affect the biological or physiological bases of
human motivation, either through drugs, or through
genetic selection or engineering, or by using
external devices that affect the brain or the
learning process. We could use these techniques to
overcome the moral and psychological shortcomings
that imperil the human species. We are at the early
stages of such research, but there are few cogent
philosophical or moral objections to the use of
specifically biomedical moral enhancement –
or moral bioenhancement. In fact, the risks
we face are so serious that it is imperative we
explore every possibility of developing moral
bioenhancement technologies – not to replace
traditional moral education, but to complement it.
We simply can’t afford to miss opportunities. We
have provided ourselves with the tools to end
worthwhile life on Earth forever. Nuclear war, with
the weapons already in existence today could achieve
this alone. If we must possess such a formidable
power, it should be entrusted only to those who are
both morally enlightened and adequately informed.
Objection 1:
Too Little, Too Late?
We already
have the weapons, and we are already on the path to
disastrous climate change, so perhaps there is not
enough time for this enhancement to take place.
Moral educators have existed within societies across
the world for thousands of years – Buddha, Confucius
and Socrates, to name only three – yet we still lack
the basic ethical skills we need to ensure our own
survival is not jeopardised. As for moral
bioenhancement, it remains a field in its infancy.
We do not
dispute this. The relevant research is in its
inception, and there is no guarantee that it will
deliver in time, or at all. Our claim is merely that
the requisite moral enhancement is theoretically
possible – in other words, that we are not
biologically or genetically doomed to cause our own
destruction – and that we should do what we can to
achieve it.
Objection 2:
The Bootstrapping Problem
We face an
uncomfortable dilemma as we seek out and implement
such enhancements: they will have to be developed
and selected by the very people who are in need of
them, and as with all science, moral bioenhancement
technologies will be open to abuse, misuse or even a
simple lack of funding or resources.
The risks
of misapplying any powerful technology are serious.
Good moral reasoning was often overruled in small
communities with simple technology, but now failure
of morality to guide us could have cataclysmic
consequences. A turning point was reached at the
middle of the last century with the invention of the
atomic bomb. For the first time, continued
technological progress was no longer clearly to the
overall advantage of humanity. That is not to say we
should therefore halt all scientific endeavour. It
is possible for humankind to improve
morally to the extent that we can use our new and
overwhelming powers of action for the better. The
very progress of science and technology increases
this possibility by promising to supply new
instruments of moral enhancement, which could be
applied alongside traditional moral education.
Objection 3:
Liberal Democracy – a Panacea?
In recent
years we have put a lot of faith in the power of
democracy. Some have even argued that democracy will
bring an ‘end’ to history, in the sense that it will
end social and political development by reaching its
summit. Surely democratic decision-making, drawing
on the best available scientific evidence, will
enable government action to avoid the looming
threats to our future, without any need for moral
enhancement?
In fact, as
things stand today, it seems more likely that
democracy will bring history to an end in a
different sense: through a failure to mitigate
human-induced climate change and environmental
degradation. This prospect is bad enough, but
increasing scarcity of natural resources brings an
increased risk of wars, which, with our weapons of
mass destruction, makes complete destruction only
too plausible.
Sometimes
an appeal is made to the so-called ‘jury theorem’ to
support the prospect of democracy reaching the right
decisions: even if voters are on average only
slightly more likely to get a choice right than
wrong – suppose they are right 51% of the time –
then, where there is a sufficiently large numbers of
voters, a majority of the voters (ie, 51%) is almost
certain to make the right choice.
However, if
the evolutionary biases we have already mentioned –
our parochial altruism and bias towards the near
future – influence our attitudes to climatic and
environmental policies, then there is good reason to
believe that voters are more likely to get it wrong
than right. The jury theorem then means it’s almost
certain that a majority will opt for the wrong
policies! Nor should we take it for granted that the
right climatic and environmental policy will always
appear in manifestoes. Powerful business interests
and mass media control might block effective
environmental policy in a market economy.
Conclusion
Modern
technology provides us with many means to cause our
downfall, and our natural moral psychology does not
provide us with the means to prevent it. The moral
enhancement of humankind is necessary for there to
be a way out of this predicament. If we are to avoid
catastrophe by misguided employment of our power, we
need to be morally motivated to a higher degree (as
well as adequately informed about relevant facts). A
stronger focus on moral education could go some way
to achieving this, but as already remarked, this
method has had only modest success during the last
couple of millennia. Our growing knowledge of
biology, especially genetics and neurobiology, could
deliver additional moral enhancement, such as drugs
or genetic modifications, or devices to augment
moral education.
The
development and application of such techniques is
risky – it is after all humans in their current
morally-inept state who must apply them – but we
think that our present situation is so desperate
that this course of action must be investigated.
We have
radically transformed our social and natural
environments by technology, while our moral
dispositions have remained virtually unchanged. We
must now consider applying technology to our own
nature, supporting our efforts to cope with the
external environment that we have created.
Biomedical
means of moral enhancement may turn out to be no
more effective than traditional means of moral
education or social reform, but they should not be
rejected out of hand. Advances are already being
made in this area. However, it is too early to
predict how, or even if, any moral bioenhancement
scheme will be achieved. Our ambition is not to
launch a definitive and detailed solution to climate
change or other mega-problems. Perhaps there is no
realistic solution. Our ambition at this point is
simply to put moral enhancement in general, and
moral bioenhancement in particular, on the table.
Last century we spent vast amounts of resources
increasing our ability to cause great harm. It would
be sad if, in this century, we reject opportunities
to increase our capacity to create benefits, or at
least to prevent such harm.
Julian Savulescu is a Professor of Philosophy at
Oxford University and Ingmar Persson is a Professor
of Philosophy at the University of Gothenburg. This
article is drawn from their book
Unfit for the Future: The Urgent Need
for Moral Enhancement,
which will be published in July by Oxford University
Press.
© Prof.
Julian Savulescu and Prof. Ingmar Persson 2012
©
Philosophy Now 2016. All rights reserved |