The Shaping of American Character
By Arthur D. RobbinsDecember 10, 2015 "Information
Clearing House" - Have you ever thought
that who you are as a person is determined in part by the government
you live under? Political philosophers have been considering such a
possibility going all the way back to the early Greeks. Government
shapes us either by engaging and empowering us through participation
or by assuming all power unto itself and leaving us to go our
separate ways alone and isolated.
Ambrogio Lorenzetti was a fourteenth-century
Italian painter. Between 1338 and 1340, he painted a series of
frescoes on three walls of the Palazzo Pubblico in Siena. The panels
are commonly known as “Allegory of Good Government,” “Effects of
Good Government on Town and Country,” and “Allegory of Bad
Government and Its Effects on Town and Country.” The paintings grace
the walls of the room where the chief magistrates of Siena held
their meetings. Their dominance of the space serves as an
inescapable reminder to all who gather there that government does
matter, that it can have both good and bad effects.
One can well imagine how the effects of good
government are portrayed. The buildings are solid. People in the
square are dancing, plying their trades. Similarly, the rolling
hills of the Tuscan countryside are lovingly depicted. The fields
are verdant. Workers are tilling the land. An allegorical figure of
security hovers above the landscape. Under bad government, the
buildings are in disrepair, the fields are barren. Symbolic
representations of evil prevail. The mood is dark and somber. Such
is the contrast between good and bad government, a contrast that
prevails as much today as when these paintings were executed.
Government and character
Plato took up the same theme. He was keenly aware
that government shapes the character of the governed. His republic
was set up with a few active, intellectually alive rulers at the top
and all the rest passive characters who knew their role in society,
never veered from it, never questioned, never sought to become
actively involved in the process of governing. That was Plato’s
ideal.
Plato speculated on what kind of characters would
prevail if this ideal were not reached or if the ideal were attained
and then deteriorated to a less-than-ideal form. He reasoned that in
these less-than-ideal forms of government, it is the preponderance
of a certain kind of individual that produces a certain government,
rather than the other way round. Nonetheless, there is a direct
correlation between a certain form of government and a certain kind
of character.
In the republic, the ideal government, the
dominant value is love of reason. The first phase of decline leads
to timocracy. In this form of government, love of honor replaces
love of reason as the dominant motive. In timocracy, active
characters prevail. The men are ambitious and competitive. There is
a hunger for war and glory. Sparta offers the obvious example.
Next in line is the oligarchy, or
plutocracy—government of the few. Under this government, men are
driven by a need for wealth. The rich become competitive with each
other in the acquisition and consumption of wealth. Reason and
ambition are harnessed to the pursuit of wealth. As materialism
spreads through the society and the rich rise in social esteem,
there is a decline in virtue. The unity of the state is compromised.
The rich are in conflict with the poor, each plotting against the
other. As they age and continue to spend and consume, these
plutocrats either spend what they have and become beggars or else
they become criminals.
As government falls into decline from the ideal of
the republic, first to timocracy, then to oligarchy, then to
democracy, there is a corresponding internal struggle within the
spirit or soul of the citizen that leads to the defeat of certain
virtues or appetites and the ascendancy of others, less desirable.
“Knowledge, right principles, true thoughts, are not at their post;
and the place lies open to the assault of false and presumptuous
notions.” In the case of the democrat, modesty and self control “are
thrust out into exile,” to be replaced by “Insolence, Anarchy, Waste
and Impudence.”
Recall that Plato had nothing but contempt for
democracy. His revulsion was no doubt a consequence of the fact that
democracy was not the outcome of abstract speculation but in fact
was the government he lived under in Athens. His daily encounters
with people he considered to be beneath him could only reinforce
his theoretical objection to this form of government.
Writing in the nineteenth century, John Stuart
Mill took up the same theme, the relationship between character and
government. The merit of political institutions, he says, consists
in part “of the degree in which they promote the general mental
advancement of the community, including under that phrase
advancement in intellect, in virtue, and in practical activity and
efficiency.”
Mill’s thoughts hearken back to Lorenzetti’s
frescoes, where one sees the direct effect of government on the
well-being of those who are governed. “A government is to be
judged,” says Mill, “by its action upon men, . . . by what it makes
of the citizens, and what it does with them; its tendency to improve
or deteriorate the people themselves.” In other words, government
shapes our character, values, and intellect. It can affect us
positively or negatively. When political institutions are ill
constructed, “the effect is felt in a thousand ways in lowering the
morality and deadening the intelligence and activity of the
people”(Mill, 210-211).
Mill describes what it is like to live under a
good despotism. The citizenry has handed its destiny over to the
government, which ministers to its needs without consultation or
involvement. This would seem to be a desirable state of affairs. But
as Mill sees it, there are negative consequences. “Leaving things to
the Government, like leaving them to Providence, is synonymous with
caring nothing about them, and accepting their results, when
disagreeable, as visitations of nature.” People become mentally
passive. Their intellect declines. Purpose in life is reduced to
“the material interests . . . to the amusement and ornamentation, of
private life. . . . The era of national decline has arrived” (ibid.,
220).
Thus, the moral fiber of the individual citizens
and of the nation taken as a collective are a consequence of the
degree of honest involvement in government by those who are
governed. According to Mill, the logical conclusion is that a
“completely popular government . . . promotes a better and higher
form of national character, than any other polity whatsoever”
(ibid., 224).
If government helps to shape character, then we
need to decide what kind of character we prefer, “that which
struggles against evils, or that which endures them; that which
bends to circumstances, or that which endeavours to make
circumstances bend to itself.” As Mill points out, there is a
general appeal to the passive type. The passive citizen is less a
menace to those who govern and less a menace to his neighbor, who
feels content to be surrounded by passive souls who offer no threat
of competition or agitation. Contentment is the goal. However, if
our intention is the improvement of mankind, active, “uncontented
characters” are our only allies (ibid., 227).
William Godwin, [147] writing
more than a half-century earlier, at the time of the French
Revolution, expressed similar sentiments. We need to consider, he
said, that “politics and modes of government will educate and infect
us all.” ( Godwin, Book I,4) We need to understand that indeed
government conduct [148] has intellectual, moral,
psychological, and emotional consequences for its citizens—that,
“perhaps it insinuates itself into our personal dispositions, and
insensibly communicates its own spirit to our private transactions”
(ibid., Book 1, 1). What we consider to be our political education
is, in effect, “the modification our ideas received from the form of
government under which we live” (ibid., Book 1, 4).
[149]
Max Weber, writing more than a century later, at
the time of the German defeat in World War I, makes the same point.
It was the politicians who failed the public. They were lacking in
“character,” he says, character “in the purely political sense of
the word, which has nothing to do with private morality. Nor was it
by chance that they lacked it; it was the result, rather, of the
structure of the state”(emphasis in original) (Weber, 205).
Government creates character. Different governments produce
different characters, some better, some worse.
In his introduction to Aristotle’s Politics,
Richard McKeon states, “There is no simple relation between ethics,
which is part of political science, and political science conceived
as the study of the state, for the state influences the education
and formation of its citizens and the character of its citizens
determines the constitution of the state” (McKeon, 548). Says
Aristotle, himself, it is the job of the legislator to see to it
that citizens “become good men. . . . The citizen should be molded
to suit the form of government under which he lives. . . . The
character of democracy creates democracy, and the character of
oligarchy creates oligarchy; and always the better the character,
the better the government” (Aristotle, 288, 300). Or, in the words
of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, “I had come to see that everything was
radically connected with politics, and that however one proceeded,
no people would be other than the nature of its government”(Barber,
213, fn 1).
Fifth century Athenian democracy produced citizens
who were robust, self-assured, independent, civic minded, courageous
in defense of their way of life. Open-minded and tolerant they were
quite comfortable seeing their leaders and their gods satirized. No
one was too important or too powerful to be poked fun at. Nothing
was sacred. Even in times of war, freedom of speech was tolerated,
as can be seen in the plays of Aristophanes.
Athenians attained a considerable degree of
literary and intellectual sophistication. Routinely, they showed
their understanding and appreciation of some of the finest plays
know to the western world, plays by writers like Aeschylus,
Sophicles, Euripedes, Aristophanes. It can reasonably be argued that
their form of government, which encouraged active, meaningful
involvement of all citizens, played an important role in the
development of the Athenian’s character and intellect.
As the structure of government underwent
fundamental changes from fifth-century B.C. Athens to fourth-century
B.C. Athens, there was a corresponding change in the intellect,
culture, and character of its citizens. As Athenian democratic
government entered a period of decline, subsequent to defeat in its
war against Sparta, the individual Athenian retreated into a more
self-centered way of life. Citizenship weakened. Private life began
to take precedence over public life. Commitment to the common good
diminished.
Writing of Germany in the late nineteenth century,
under the powerful autocrat Otto von Bismarck, Max Weber shows how a
nation loses its political will when the citizenry lacks the
opportunity to share responsibility for its own political fate.
Weber describes the awkwardness of the average German traveling to
other countries:
Deprived of the accustomed carapace of
bureaucratic regimentation, [they] lose all sense of direction
and security—a consequence of being accustomed to regard
themselves at home merely as the object of the way their lives
are ordered rather than as responsible for it themselves. This
is the reason for that insecure, self-conscious way of
presenting themselves in public which is definitely the source
of the Germans’ much criticized over-familiarity. In as much as
it exists, their political “immaturity” results from the
uncontrolled rule of officialdom, and from the fact that the
ruled are accustomed to submit to that rule without themselves
sharing responsibility (Weber, 268-269).
Such generalizations could apply to any culture at
any time. One’s sense of self and level of self-confidence are
determined, in part, by the government one lives under. This becomes
much harder to grasp as we change our focus to our own culture and
our own time. Yet it is as true today as it was twenty-five hundred
years ago in Athens, or more than a century ago in Germany.
The United States offers an interesting case study
in government and its effects, largely because this country started
from scratch with a particular form of government—a constitutional
oligarchy (P.D.–) with strong emphasis on rhetorical democracy
(R.D.+). [150] And further, in early American
history, there was a change in government that parallels the change
in Athens from the fifth to the fourth centuries. Between 1776, when
the thirteen colonies became thirteen states, each with its own form
of government, and 1787, when the U.S. Constitution was ratified,
there was a period of experimentation in government. Democratic
values were on the rise. Citizens were actively involved in shaping
their own political destinies. Then the Constitution put in place a
centralized government with power concentrated in the hands of a
few. The result was a notable change in the culture, character, and
intellect of the citizenry.
The paltry American
If we would like to know something about the
character and intellect of the average American in the early 1800s,
Alexis de Tocqueville’s Democracy in America is one of our
best resources. It is important to remember that Tocqueville was an
aristocrat and that his bias is reflected in his attitude toward
American culture. Nonetheless, I believe that his descriptions and
insights are uncanny and startling in their validity more than one
hundred fifty years later, all the more so when one takes into
account that he was twenty-seven years old at the time of his
American visit.
However, Tocqueville is confused on the subject of
democracy. He repeatedly makes broad generalizations about
“democracy” based on his observations in the United States. But the
country he visited was not a political democracy. It was an
oligarchy. If we substitute the word “oligarchy” for “democracy,” we
can gain a clear sense of why the typical American has ended up the
way Tocqueville describes him.
Tocqueville ascribes what is wrong with America to
“equality.” The equality he has in mind, however, is not the
political equality that would prevail in a democracy, but “equality
of condition,” that is, social equality.
[151]
As Tocqueville sees it, the leveling effect of
social equality has a deleterious effect on individual and social
development. Everyone is like everyone else. Character and culture
settle into a condition of mediocrity. If only there were an
aristocracy, says Tocqueville, American culture would be
qualitatively richer, the typical American more profound in his
thought and emotion.
While Tocqueville’s observations are accurate, I
believe his attribution of causality is in error. The Americans he
observed were the way they were not because they were socially equal
but because they lived in an oligarchy, which afforded them little
or no opportunity to develop their capacity for abstract thought the
way the Athenians did.
The typical American, as observed by Tocqueville
in the 1830s, is weak and isolated, plagued with feelings of
insignificance. “Everyone shuts himself up tightly within himself
and insists upon judging the world from there”(Tocqueville, vol. 2,
4). As an American in the twenty-first century, one might cringe at
the following observation: “Nothing conceivable is so petty, so
insipid, so crowded with paltry interests—in one word, so
anti-poetic—as the life of a man in the United States” (ibid., 78).
I’m afraid the word “anti-poetic” truly does apply.
Because Americans are so focused on their own
comforts and material success, they lack breadth of vision and depth
of insight. The literature produced under such circumstances will be
geared more toward dazzling than toward developing a deeper
appreciation for its aesthetic qualities. [152]
“The object of authors will be to astonish rather than to please,
and to stir their passions more than to charm their taste” (ibid.,
63). Readers treat their authors as do kings their courtiers: “They
enrich and despise them” (ibid., 64).
Under such circumstances, independent thought will
be at a minimum. Not only is there a lack of time and peace of mind,
as well as lack of an interested public, there is also the enormous
weight of a multitude in agreement with each other on what is and is
not an acceptable idea. Says Tocqueville, “the power exercised by
the mass upon the mind of each individual is extremely great.” One
does not need oppressive laws and censorship to discourage new ideas
and critical thinking. “Public disapprobation is enough; a sense of
their loneliness [that of independent thinkers] and impotence
overtakes them and drives them to despair” (ibid., 275).
Tocqueville draws a contrast between life under a
monarch and life under the kind of government he sees in the United
States. Under a monarch, oppression was material, directed against
the body itself: “The body was attacked to subdue the soul; but the
soul escaped the blows which were directed against it and rose
proudly superior.” Such, he says, is not the case under a
“democracy” (oligarchy, in fact). There the body is left free and
the soul is enslaved. The master no longer says, “You shall think as
I do or you shall die.” Instead, he says:
You are free to think differently from me and
retain your life, your property and all that you possess; but
you are henceforth a stranger among your people. . . . Your
fellow creatures will shun you like an impure being; . . . Go in
peace! I have given you your life, but it is an existence worse
than death (ibid., vol. 1, 274-275).
[153]
The collective repression of intellect and
critical thinking [154] leads to a weakening and
debasement of character. There is a lack of courage, a lack of
independent thought that contrasts with what had been the case in an
earlier time. Tocqueville notes, “I found very few men who displayed
that manly candor and masculine independence of opinion which
frequently distinguished the Americans in former times, and which
constitutes the leading feature in distinguished characters wherever
they may be found” (ibid., 277). [155]
Tocqueville finds Americans to be practical, small
minded, and lacking in self-awareness and awareness of the
sensitivities and needs of their fellow citizens. [156]
This is so, he says, because in a democratic (i.e.,
oligarchic) community, “each citizen is habitually engaged in the
contemplation of a very puny subject: namely, himself ” (ibid., vol.
2, 83). Needless to say, the American who thinks little of his
fellow citizen has even less concern with those who live in
countries other than his own. “An American leaves his country with a
heart swollen with pride; on arriving in Europe, he at once finds
out that we are not so engrossed by the United States and the great
people who inhabit it as he had supposed; and this begins to annoy
him” (ibid., 183).
Tocqueville detects “a strange melancholy” among
the Americans. [157] This he attributes to the fact
that though they attain an equality of condition, they always want
more. “It perpetually retires before them, yet without hiding itself
from sight, and in retiring draws them on. . . . They are near
enough to see its charms, but too far off to enjoy them; and before
they have tasted its delights, they die”(ibid., 147). In a similar
vein, Tocqueville observes that the American “clutches everything .
. . [but] holds nothing” (ibid., 144). He is at once “independent
but powerless” (ibid., 311). He is near people but not connected to
them. “He is close to them, but does not see them; he touches them,
but he does not feel them; he exists only in himself and for himself
alone” (ibid., 336).
The lonely American
It is enlightening to compare Tocqueville’s
critique of the American character with the thoughts of the American
transcendental philosopher Ralph Waldo Emerson (1803–1882). Writing
at the same time as Tocqueville, Emerson echoes Tocqueville’s
thoughts, but with approval, not condemnation. In Emerson’s
writings, the individual is portrayed as being detached and isolated
from others. What, in fact, has its locus outside the head, in the
world of human interaction and public affairs, is internalized. The
individual becomes “self-possessed.” He becomes his own private
property. He is his own self-contained nation-state, wanting nothing
from the external world. [158]
Emerson was a loner and an isolate and developed a
philosophy of life that consecrated the individual’s separateness
and lack of community involvement. “Let man stand erect, go alone,
and possess the universe.” (Emerson, Journals, v01.3, 99)
“Build therefore your own world” (Emerson, Essays, 38). “Do
not seek yourself outside yourself” [“Ne te quaesiveris extra”]
(ibid., 77). “Man,” we learn, “is insular and cannot be touched . .
. and holds his individual being on that condition” (Emerson,
Selections, 61). These are the words of a man unto himself, for
himself, by himself, who believes that by extension that is where we
all belong. This, as Tocqueville would see it, describes the typical
American.
Writing in 1970, Philip E. Slater, in The
Pursuit of Loneliness, offers a description of the American
character that resonates with the thoughts of Tocqueville and
Emerson, thoughts that were penned some one hundred forty years
earlier. Basically, as Slater sees it, Americans are lonely,
isolated, and bereft of emotion. “Re-entering America, one is struck
first of all by the grim monotony of American facial
expressions—hard, surly and bitter—and the aura of deprivation that
informs them.” (Slater, xii). Here we have another witness.
Anaïs Nin (1903–1977) is the author of published
journals that span more than sixty years, beginning when she was
eleven years old and ending shortly before her death. Nin was born
in France and immigrated to the United States with her mother and
two brothers in 1914, at the age of eleven. About a decade later,
after marrying, she returned to France. Subsequently, she made
return trips to the United States, where she ultimately spent the
last part of her life. Nin is an astute observer with extensive
experience in both Europe and the United States. She draws a
contrast between Paris and New York:
In Paris, when entering a room, everyone pays
attention, seeks to make you feel welcome, to enter into
conversation, is curious, responsive. Here it seems everyone is
pretending not to see, hear or look too intently. The faces
reveal no interest, no responsiveness.
Overtones are missing. Relationships seem
impersonal and everyone conceals his secret life, whereas in
Paris it was the exciting substance of our talks, intimate
revelations and sharing of experience (Nin, vol. 3, 14).
Nin expresses her concern over the American “cult
of toughness, its hatred of sensitivity” and issues a warning:
“Someday [America] may have to pay a terrible price for this,
because atrophy of feeling creates criminals” (ibid., 28).
Here is another vignette, written in 1940:
No place to sit and talk. You are rushed by
the waitress. The radios blare so loudly one is deafened. The
lights stun you. Noise and light amplified until the senses
become dulled. . . .
In Europe the machines are killing people.
Here the machines seem to have dehumanized people. There are few
amenities, the softening use of courtesy to palliate the
cruelties of life. Under the guise of honesty people are brutal
to each other (ibid., 34).
This lonely, empty, harsh feeling is a consequence
of the pursuit of a separate, private life of self-sufficiency, from
which community and collective needs are excluded, says Slater. “We
seek more and more privacy and feel more and more alienated and
lonely when we get it”(Slater, 7). The suburban ideal, which so many
Americans pursue, Slater describes as follows:
The suburban dweller seeks peace, privacy,
nature, community, and a child-rearing environment which is
healthy and culturally optimal. Instead he finds neither the
beauty and serenity of the countryside, the stimulation of the
city, nor the stability and sense of community of the small
town, and his children are exposed to a cultural deprivation
equaling that of any slum child with a television set (ibid.,
9). [159]
The pursuit of the American dream has its roots in
the need to escape, evade, and avoid (ibid., 131). As a consequence,
the capacities to enjoy and attain fulfillment are stunted.
Americans have a craving to belong but “have a profound tendency to
feel like outsiders—they wonder where the action is and wander about
in search of it” (ibid., 110). The isolation and passivity lead to
feelings of powerlessness, which the American devotes himself to
denying and escaping. [160]
Americans are insecure, constantly in pursuit of a
feeling of security, which they never attain. There is an underlying
anxiety that leans toward paranoia. According to Slater, “Americans
devote more of their collective resources to security than any other
need.” (ibid., 1). The unrelenting anti-Communism of the 1950s could
be offered as one example of this phenomenon. The current concern
with “terrorism” is another. The ease with which Americans commit
themselves to a course of war and killing is another illustration of
their continual attempts to achieve safety and security.
An inner sense of vague foreboding leads Americans
to acquiesce to just about any government action that makes them
feel better. Torture—which had been consigned to a time of primitive
barbarism—is currently openly acknowledged, debated, and accepted by
many. Americans are even willing to see their basic civil rights
abrogated, all in the hope of squelching the ever-present anxiety.
The Patriot Act, signed into law on October 26, 2001, allows for the
indefinite detention of immigrants; searches of homes or businesses
without warrant; and searches of telephone, e-mail, medical,
financial, and library records. [161]
Americans are fearful and they are angry. Deep
down they are angry with government/parent for lying to them and
betraying them. But the anger rarely, if ever, is outwardly directed
at the government. Instead, it is taken out on immigrants,
foreigners, racial minorities, and enemies real or imagined. For
years, the American government has indefinitely held foreign
nationals deemed to be “terrorists,” without charges and without
trials, subjecting them to torture and other inhumane treatment.
The United States spends more on its military than
the other countries of the world combined. It has about a quarter
million troops stationed in one hundred thirty countries. By 1990,
Pentagon property was valued at $1 trillion. The U.S. military
controls 18 million acres of land worldwide. With 5.1 million
employees, it is the nation’s largest employer (Berman, 143).
The credulous American
Here is another portrait of the American
character, this one even more recent. With a book bearing the
foreboding title Dark Ages America: The Final Phase of Empire
(2006), Morris Berman, like Philip Slater, continues with the same
motifs initially identified by Tocqueville.
[162]
Americans are lost and alone, clinging to what
eludes them. Speaking for Americans, Berman declares, “We are
desperate today for community because we have been lonely and
alienated for so long” (ibid., 239). He paraphrases Mother Teresa’s
view on America’s spiritual poverty: “America’s poverty . . . is
worse than that of India’s, for it is that of a terrible loneliness
that comes from wanting the wrong things” (ibid, 237).
As but one example, Berman cites an incident in
Orange City, Florida. On November 28, 2003, Walmart had a sale. A
woman was trampled to a state of unconsciousness by the stampede of
eager shoppers. They wouldn’t even move aside for rescue workers,
who found the victim slumped over, clutching her DVD player—an apt
expression of the selfish individualism of the average American.
When it gets down to basics, says Berman, “America is about as
diverse as a one string guitar” (ibid., 240).
For many Americans, the isolation, the loneliness,
brings out a craving for something bigger, an all-encompassing
belief to hold on to and bring meaning to their lives. This is where
the myth of America comes into play, erected on a foundation of
rhetorical democracy. Thus, though Americans are denied the
opportunity to govern themselves and are cut loose from meaningful
connections to community and one another, they believe that they are
living in a democratic nation and that their democratic values are
what set them apart from the rest of humanity and endow them with
the holy mission of saving the world. “Americanism, in short: that
is our religion,” says Berman(ibid., 249).
Religion does not admit of analysis or critique,
which is why Americans are incapable of taking an objective,
analytic look at their culture and government. One does not question
the beneficence of one’s government and its leaders. As Berman
points out, only in America is it possible to be “un-American” by
disagreeing with one’s government. There is no such thing as being
“un-Italian” or “un-Danish”(ibid., 284).
Americans, as a rule, are very gullible and hence
easy to manipulate. They believe what their government, via the
media, tells them to believe. Anyone who thinks otherwise is a
“conspiracy nut.” Berman puts it bluntly: “in other countries
grown-ups know there is no truth teat to suck on” (ibid., 282).
Like small children, Americans trust their
parents—that is, their government and the people who speak for
it—and like small children they have a desperate need to be taken
care of, to be “okay.” They believe what the commercials tell them
about various drugs and foods, usually unquestioningly, frequently
with dire consequences for their mental and physical health.
Bombarded with endless amounts of “information,” Americans are
notoriously ignorant about the world they live in, including and
especially their own country.
Berman, like other writers, makes reference to
“the endless restlessness that is so characteristic of
America”(ibid., 252) and observes that though they are always on the
move, Americans are “extremely nervous about real change” (ibid.,
253). He offers this quote from the American poet W. H. Auden, from
“The Age of Anxiety”: “We would rather be ruined than changed”
(ibid., 236).
Berman also quotes Nicholas von Hoffman, who
describes Americans as living in a glass dome, a sort of terrarium,
cut off from reality and the outside world. “Bobbleheads in
Bubbleland,” Hoffman calls them. “They shop in bubbled malls, they
live in gated communities, and they move from place to place
breathing their own, private air, in the bubble-mobiles known as
SUVs” (ibid., 282).
It is not surprising that, living in isolation, in
“Bubbleland,” Americans are anxious, insecure, and fearful. From
such a condition—in which one is detached from community both
national and international, ignorant of the various political forces
at play, subject to manipulation by the media on behalf of a
government that wishes to intimidate as a means of exercising
control—it is not surprising that Americans should be prone to
violence. The detachment, the separation from and misunderstanding
of the root causes of power dynamics, results in chronic insecurity
and the need to defend oneself against unseen enemies.
The homicide rate in the European Union between
1979–1999 was 1.7 per one hundred thousand. In the United States, it
was 6.26. In Europe, there is deep-seated opposition to the death
penalty. Two-thirds of Americans are in favor of it. The United
States routinely engages in ruthless repressions and violent wars on
a sustained basis, for the most part unchallenged by the populace
whose taxes fund them.
The depleted American
Reluctantly, I must agree with three thoughtful
writers who have reached the same conclusion over a span of close to
one hundred fifty years. Americans are isolated, anxious, insecure,
and lonely. One might also argue that the culture that has developed
has become what it is so as to provide escape from these very
unpleasant conditions. So, if one were to query the average
American, putting aside for a moment the economic hardships that
persist in 2014, that American might describe himself as the
happiest person on earth. Such a response has its basis in denial
and the perpetual distraction that contemporary culture provides.
The American doesn’t know his true feelings and doesn’t want to.
One might also reasonably argue that Americans are
the way they are because their form of government excludes them from
the possibility of the participation that would bring them back to
the community in an active way, expanding their emotional and
intellectual horizons. After all, as Tocqueville observes, “Feelings
and opinions are recruited, the heart is enlarged, and the human
mind is developed only by the reciprocal influence of men upon one
another”(Tocqueville, vol. 2, 117).
Using the United States as his point of reference,
and once again misapplying the word “democracy,” Tocqueville makes
some thoughtful observations on the relationship between the
individual and the state. He says, “In a democratic [read
oligarchic] community individuals are very weak, but the state,
which represents them all and contains them all in its grasp, is
very powerful. . . . In democratic [read oligarchic] communities the
imagination is compressed when men think of themselves; it expands
indefinitely when they think of the state” (ibid., 56).
One could revise what Tocqueville has said as
follows: ‘In a constitutional oligarchy, spread across a vast land
mass, where power and control are highly centralized, individuals
are very weak.’ I think this is an important observation and helps
to explain a lot of what has been said about the insecurity,
loneliness, and sense of isolation that seem to characterize the
average American. He is made to feel small and powerless by the very
existence of a large, powerful central government over which he has
no control. He becomes weak and enervated, for “extreme
centralization of government ultimately enervates society” (ibid.,
317).
Where there is a big, powerful central government,
run by a small oligarchy sharing common interests, and a vast mass
of undifferentiated individuals with no valid means for exercising
political power, the political situation can easily slide into
despotism. Tocqueville sees a self-enhancing process:
Thus the vices which despotism produces are
precisely those which equality fosters. These two things
perniciously complete and assist each other. Equality places men
side by side, unconnected by any common tie; despotism raises
barriers to keep them asunder; the former disposes them not to
consider their fellow creatures, the latter makes general
indifference a sort of public virtue (ibid., 109).
The equality Tocqueville refers to—equality of
condition—probably never existed to the degree he thinks it did.
Even in colonial days, there was gross disparity in wealth, a
condition that became more pronounced with the passing of the years.
But, more importantly, there is nothing about equality of condition
that should keep men asunder. Rather, it is the political condition
Tocqueville aptly describes that creates a situation favorable to
the emergence of despotism: strong, central government and a mass of
individuals with no significant political means at their disposal.
Lacking a true political life, people focus
instead on success in business and the pursuit of personal pleasure
in their private lives. “They lose sight of the close connection
that exists between the private fortune of each and the prosperity
of all.” Under such circumstances, one would not have to do violence
to deprive them of the rights they enjoy: “they themselves willingly
loosen their hold” (ibid., 149).
Having the freedom to pursue one’s private
interests undisturbed leads to a dread of anarchy, a fear that is
sparked by the slightest public commotion. As Tocqueville puts it,
men are willing “to fling away their freedom at the first
disturbance.” A nation that asks nothing of its government but
public tranquility and order “is already a slave at heart, the slave
of its own well-being, awaiting only the hand that will bind it.”
The universal pursuit of private interest leaves an open path to
“the smallest parties” who seek to get the upper hand:
A multitude represented by a few players, who
alone speak the name of an absent or inattentive crowd: they
alone are in action, while all others are stationary; they
regulate everything by their own caprice; they change the laws
and tyrannize at will over the manners of the country; and then
men wonder to see into how small a number of weak and worthless
hands a great people may fall (ibid., 150).
Is this not the current condition in the United
States? A handful of oligarchs have squandered trillions of dollars
on banking interests and foreign wars. Legislation is passed that
more and more limits the opportunity to enjoy one’s civil rights and
engage in meaningful political activity.
Americans are cowed by the latest threats of
terrorism and pandemic. All of this is the consequence not of
democracy, which was explicitly eliminated from consideration by the
clique of men who engineered the writing and ratification of the
U.S. Constitution. Instead, it is the consequence of a small
oligarchy, ruling a vast nation, in which the citizenry has
atrophied into a mass of passive, frightened men and women, in the
absence of a viable political alternative to the despotism they are
living under and don’t even understand.
As Tocqueville points out, there are two kinds of
tyranny. Under the Roman emperors, tyranny was odious and obvious.
It “was extremely onerous to the few, but it did not reach the
many.” Of a different nature is tyranny under a constitutional
oligarchy, such as exists in the United States. This tyranny “would
be more extensive and more mild; it would degrade men without
tormenting them” (ibid., 335). It would be something like living
under the tutelage of a parent.
However, this is not the parent who seeks to
prepare his children for adulthood and then liberate them. This is
the parent who seeks to keep the child perpetually passive and
dependent. Living in this setting—in which the government ostensibly
ministers to the children’s needs, controls and oversees their
actions—“what remains, but to spare them all the care of thinking
and all the trouble of living”? Such a tyranny “every day renders
the exercise of the free agency of man less useful and less
frequent; it circumscribes the will within a narrower range and
gradually robs a man of all uses of himself”(ibid., 336-337).
The persistent sense of a lurking presence, the
need to conform and acquiesce so as not to trouble the parent who
watches over and protects him, the possibility of action leading to
independence and adulthood having been eliminated, man is reduced to
a state of flabby self-indulgence, which he labels “freedom.” In the
grips of such a presence, Tocqueville tells us:
The will of man is not shattered, but
softened, bent, and guided; men are seldom forced by it to act,
but they are constantly restrained from acting. Such a power
does not destroy, but it prevents existence; it does not
tyrannize, but it compresses, enervates, extinguishes, and
stupefies a people, till [the] nation is reduced to nothing
better than a flock of timid and industrious animals, of which
the government is the shepherd (ibid., 337).
[163]
The power to bend an entire nation to such
tutelage requires deception. The population submits so gently
because it believes it is doing so voluntarily. This is where the
notion of “popular sovereignty” comes in. Always remember, the voice
of government tells us, that you, the people, rule and that you, the
people, choose your rulers. Thus, Tocqueville explains, “Every man
allows himself to be put in leading-strings, because he sees [that
is, he believes] that it is not a person or a class of persons, but
the people at large who hold the end of his chain.” By such a system
as this—through elections—“the people shake off their state of
dependence just long enough to select their master and then relapse
into it again” (ibid.).
Writing more than one hundred fifty years ago,
when the electorate was probably more cognizant of its political
potential and less thoroughly lulled into a state of quiescence than
it is today, Tocqueville could nonetheless declare, without
hesitation:
It is in vain to summon a people who have been
rendered so dependent on the central power to choose from time
to time the representatives of that power; this rare and brief
exercise of their free choice, however important it may be, will
not prevent them from gradually losing the faculties of
thinking, feeling and acting for themselves, and thus gradually
falling below the level of humanity (ibid., 339).
It is folly to believe that those who have been
deprived of self-government “should succeed in making a proper
choice of those by whom they are to be governed.” It is folly to
assume that a subservient people will choose to be led by “a
liberal, wise, and energetic government” (ibid.).
The trivialization of public life and its
consequences
Tocqueville set out all of this in the 1830s. C.
Wright Mills, in The Power Elite (published in 1956), more
than a century later, described in detail the same process
Tocqueville had alluded to. The individual loses his substance by
voluntarily bowing to an overpowering and distant oligarchy, while
simultaneously “participating” in sham democracy.
Mills speaks of the “grim trivialization of public
life.” He describes the election of 1954, where national issues of
substance were ignored in favor of slander and personal attack,
which initially entertained and then alienated prospective voters.
“Slogans and personal attacks on character, personal defects, and
counter-charges and suspicions were all that the electorate could
see or hear, and, as usual, many paid no attention at all” (Mills,
253). [164]
Mills hypothesizes the existence of various local
publics, or community discussion groups/parties that represent a
specific set of opinions and viewpoints. Such publics are scattered
throughout the country, interact with each other, and in some way or
another bring their beliefs to the attention of those in power.
Public opinion in this version of government has a means of bearing
down on elected officials and gaining their cooperation. The
discussions themselves, these local interactions, are the mechanism
by which the individual educates himself and articulates his
viewpoints.
This version, says Mills, is “a fairy tale.” In
fact, this “community of publics” has been transformed into a
“society of masses”(ibid., 300). Belonging to this mass serves to
annihilate the individual and his capacity for honest
self-expression. Politically, he becomes a phantom, a shadow on the
wall, and nothing more. The political process Mills describes is
more like a ballet or a silent movie than an active polity shaping
its own destiny. Everyone has a role to play in convincing himself
and the next person that democracy exists and that he is actively
participating in an act of self-government. “What the public stands
for, accordingly, is often a vagueness of policy (called
open-mindedness), a lack of involvement in public affairs (known as
reasonableness), and a professional disinterest (known as
tolerance)” (ibid., 306).
When a man is part of the masses, says Mills, he
lacks “any sense of political belonging.” He lacks the political
community, where there is shared belief in the purposes of the
organization and trust in its leadership. To have political
belonging is “to make the human association a psychological center
of one’s self, to take into our conscience, deliberately and freely,
its rules of conduct and its purposes, which we thus shape and which
in turn shape us.” This kind of political association is a place “in
which reasonable opinions can be formulated.” It is “an agency by
which reasonable activities may be undertaken.” And it is powerful
enough “to make a difference” (ibid., 308). Thus, our psychological
existence is determined, as adults in the world, by the opportunity
we are given to partake in the process of determining those policies
and acts of legislation that shape the content and context of our
social living. In the absence of such an opportunity, we cease to
exist.
As Mills saw it, the political power dynamics of
the 1950s were such that there was no opportunity for the individual
to engage in political struggle and thus develop into a full adult
with political beliefs and a sense of empowerment. What he describes
of the political culture he knew is even truer today than it was
fifty years ago. On the one hand, there is “the huge corporation,
the inaccessible government, the grim military establishment.” On
the other, we find “the family and the small community.” There is
nothing in between, “no intermediate associations in which men feel
secure and with which they feel powerful.” As a consequence, there
is “little live political struggle” (ibid.).
In such a context, where political reality has
been flattened into a two-dimensional, cardboard cutout, there
really is no such thing as “public opinion,” because there is no
genuine public, just the anonymous mass. As Mills observes, “Public
opinion exists when people who are not in the government of a
country claim the right to express political opinions freely and
publicly, and the right that these opinions should influence or
determine the policies, personnel, and actions of their government”
(ibid., 309).
As Mills makes clear, public opinion is not what
some polling organization reports to the news media after knocking
on a few doors. Public opinion has efficacy, or it is nothing. For
example, in February of 2003, millions of people demonstrated in the
United States and around the world against an invasion of Iraq. As
subsequent events have come to prove, public opinion counted for
nothing. In 2008–2009, trillions of dollars were given away to a
handful of bankers as the world economy crumbled. There is a hardly
a man or woman standing, anywhere in the world—other than the
aforementioned handful of bankers—who supported such a policy. Yet
the plunder of the public treasury continues.
Public opinion counts for nothing. The crowds
disperse, “atomized and submissive masses” (ibid.). As these
examples demonstrate, public opinion is not something to be honored
and respected, it is something to be shaped, manipulated, and
controlled, just as Edward Bernays predicted in the 1920s.
[165]
Although the conditions Mills outlines have
existed since the days of Tocqueville and even earlier, there is at
least one factor that deserves special mention: the media. Mills
uses the term “psychological illiteracy” to refer to the fact that
our knowledge of what is real in the world of politics and power is
shaped for us by the media. We have little or no first-hand
knowledge. A reality is created for us, which we come to believe in.
“Our standards of credulity, our standards of reality, tend to be
set by these media rather than by our own fragmentary experience”
(ibid., 311).
To resist the media—to see behind one reality to
the other—we need a context of meaning, which of course the media do
not supply. But if we allow ourselves to delve deeper into meanings,
if we leave the realm of stereotypes to enter the realm of real
beings and real events, we separate ourselves from those around us
and raise our level of anxiety and sense of isolation.
But if we want to free ourselves, we have to
accept the fact that there are two different realities—one that is
pleasant and comforting and the other that is devious and sinister.
We have to accept the fact that we are being lied to and
manipulated. Yet, if we are willing “to accept opinions in their
terms,” we “gain the good solid feeling of being correct without
having to think” (ibid., 312).
The media, says Mills—especially television—not
only affect how we see external reality, they affect how we see
ourselves. They give us our sense of self. They give us our
identity. Thus, if we attempt to see deeper and further, we raise
fundamental issues about who we are and how we fit in. Not a very
reassuring prospect.
And, most critically, even when the media supply
simple, accurate information about the state of the world, they
present it in such a way as to make it difficult if not impossible
for the individual “to connect his daily life with these larger
realities. They do not connect the information they provide on
public issues with the troubles felt by the individual. They do not
increase rational insight into tensions, either those in the
individual or those of the society which are reflected in the
individual” (ibid., 315)
In other words, though Americans typically feel
cut off from the world around them, in fact, they are deeply
affected by what occurs in that world. There is a connection between
the tension and suffering in the world and the tensions they feel on
a daily basis, but they have been trained to ignore the connection
and to believe that they are blissfully content in their private
universe.
The American does not understand that his personal
troubles are shared by others, that they have political
implications, that personal troubles often need to be translated
into public issues for them to be properly resolved. “They lose
sight of the close connection that exists between the private
fortune of each and the prosperity of all” (Tocqueville, vol. 2,
149).
As Mills points out, it is not only the media that
fail us in our attempts to stay connected to social reality and be
effective in shaping our destinies. Education has a large role to
play, as well. It trains us vocationally. It inculcates the values
and national loyalties required to maintain the status quo. We are
not trained to think critically, to analyze. We are trained to get
ahead. We mistake job advancement for self-development, which it is
not. “Mass education . . . has become—another mass medium” (Mills,
317). Our schools and colleges fail us. They should train us for
“the struggle for individual and public transcendence” (ibid., 319).
Instead, they school us in acquiescence, stereotypes, and blind
loyalties.
Americans lead narrow and fragmented lives.
Confined by their routines to a repetitious existence, they are
denied the opportunity for genuine discussion, debate, and conflict
of opinion—which could redirect their energies from the immediate
task at hand to the grander issues. They lack a sense of the larger
structure and their place in it. “In every major area of life, the
loss of a sense of structure and the submergence into powerless
milieux is the cardinal fact” (ibid., 321). Unable to see the whole
or his place in it, the American submits to vague inevitability that
he can neither comprehend nor avoid. There is no outer dialogue, nor
is there an inner dialogue, which we refer to as “thinking.”
Unable to transcend his daily existence, the mass
man “drifts, he fulfills habits, his behavior a result of a planless
mixture of the confused standards and the uncriticized expectations
that he has taken over from others” (ibid., 322). He loses is
self-confidence as a human being. He loses his independence. As
Tocqueville puts it, he “allows himself to be put in
leading-strings, because he sees that it is not a person or a class
of persons, but the people at large who hold the end of his
chain”(ibid., vol. 2, 337).
It is striking the degree to which Tocqueville and
Mills, with more than a century separating them, reach the same
conclusions about the nature and quality of American life. Both
identify power—power that is hidden and subtle, power that denies
itself as power—as the key ingredient in fragmenting the population,
creating a mass of “sheeple” who lack the capacity of
self-understanding both individually and collectively.
Mills differentiates between authority—power that
is visible and explicitly obeyed—and manipulation, where there is
“the ‘secret’ exercise of power, unknown to those who are
influenced”(Mills, 316). When men want to rule without seeming to do
so, probably because they cannot lay claim to the required
legitimacy, they will rule invisibly and “benignly,” shielding
themselves behind the rhetoric of popular rule. Although “authority
formally resides ‘in the people,’ . . . the power of initiation is
in fact held by small circles of men.” This is not to be known.
There is the risk that power becomes identified by its true colors.
“That is why the standard strategy of manipulation is to make it
appear that the people . . . ‘really made the decision’” (ibid.,
317).
Mills identifies “liberal rhetoric which requires
a continual flattery of the citizens” as a key ingredient in keeping
the masses quiet (ibid., 331). Such a rhetoric becomes a mask for
all political positions, a means of exercising political power
without appearing to do so. This is consistent with my earlier use
of the term “rhetorical democracy.” It is not that “the people” are
in charge, but that they are led to believe that they are. As
Tocqueville points out, since the people are submitting to their own
will, why should they in any way object?
Thus, the people are their own oppressors and, of
course, they don’t know it. They don’t know they are being
tyrannized. They think they are free. “Instead of justifying the
power of an elite by portraying it favorably, one denies that any
set of men, any class, any organization has any really consequential
power” (ibid., 336). To reiterate what Tocqueville said, “Such a
power does not destroy, but it prevents existence; it does not
tyrannize, but it compresses, enervates, extinguishes, and stupefies
a people, till [the] nation is reduced to nothing better than a
flock of timid and industrious animals, of which the government is
the shepherd” (Tocqueville, vol. 2, 337).
[166]
Sheldon Wolin (Democracy Incorporated)
has coined the term “inverted totalitarianism” to describe a form of
government that in many ways achieves the goals of totalitarianism
but by different, gentler means. Inverted totalitarianism is “driven
by abstract totalizing powers, not by personal rule.” The leader is
not the architect of the system. He is its product. He fulfills a
pre-assigned role.
The system succeeds not by activating the masses
but by doing just the opposite, “encouraging political
disengagement.” “Democracy” is encouraged, touted, both domestically
and overseas. To use Wolin’s terminology, it is “managed democracy,”
“a political form in which governments are legitimated by elections
that they have learned to control,” a form of government that
attempts to keep alive the appearance of democracy while
simultaneously defeating democracy’s primary purpose,
self-government.
In managed democracy “free politics” are
encouraged. Thus the populace is placated and pacified. Believing
that in fact they have the government they want, people are lulled
into a state of passivity and acquiescence, leaving the controlling
powers to operate as they see fit to advance their particular
interests. Democratic myths persist in the absence of true
democratic practice.
Thus there is a confluence of opinion spanning
close to one hundred eighty years concerning American character and
the government forces that shape it. We are dominated and formed by
a government that eludes our efforts to know it and bend it to our
wishes. It is a phantom government that is everywhere and nowhere at
the same time. It shunts us into a realm of confusion and fear from
which we see no escape.
Yet there is an escape. Mills has described what
needs to happen for Americans to become transformed from a herd of
sheep into a society of independent, thoughtful, politically
sophisticated individuals. They must develop ”a sense of political
belonging.” To have political belonging is “to make the human
association [i.e. political community] a psychological center of
one’s self, to take into our conscience, deliberately and freely,
its rules of conduct and its purposes, which we thus shape and which
in turn shape us.”
In
Paradise Lost, Paradise Regained: The True Meaning of Democracy,
Chapter 23, I explore in detail just how such communities are
established. Basically, it as simple as getting together with fellow
citizens on a regular basis for the purpose of discussing government
on a national level. As we hear ourselves express beliefs that have
been long dormant we start to feel alive and empowered. We listen to
others. We learn. We agree. We disagree. No longer are we isolated
and deflated. We have begun to take on a political identity, an
identity that is at the core of true adult living.
To be political is to think critically about the
government one lives under. Americans live under a constitutional
oligarchy that owes its origins to a conclave of wealthy merchants,
lawyers, speculators and aristocratic landholders who met in
Philadelphia in 1787. We revere the Constitution they created,
largely because we haven’t read the document very closely and
haven’t taken the trouble to understand its true meaning by
establishing the historical context from which it emerged.
Once we understand our government in its origins,
once we understand the forces that drove it from the outset, we will
better understand why it operates the way it does. And we will be in
a position to begin transforming our government from one that serves
the power elite into one that serves the common good.
[147]
William Godwin (1756–1836) was an English political philosopher
whose most enduring work bears the title
Enquiry Concerning Political Justice and Its Influence on Morals and
Happiness. Godwin was married to the pioneering feminist
writer Mary Wollstonecraft, who died giving birth to a daughter
named Mary, who went on to marry the poet Percy Bysshe Shelley. Mary
Shelley became a novelist and is best known for her novel
Frankenstein.
[148] Just
a reminder that the word “government” represents a concept. Concepts
cannot act. Only people can. The word “government” is thus shorthand
for “person or persons in power.”
[149] The
French philosopher Claude Adrien Helvétius (1715–1771) was similarly
concerned about the effects on government on the mentality of the
governed. He believed that we were all equally endowed with
intelligence and that differences could be explained by
circumstances. He makes special reference to the role of government:
“The inequality of intelligence that exists among men is a
consequence of the government they live under” (author’s
translation). Helvétius, De
l’Esprit, p. 180.
[150] In
Chapter 13, I differentiate among different forms of democracy,
civic democracy (C.D.), political democracy (P.D.), social democracy
(S.D.) economic democracy (E.D.) and rhetorical democracy (R.D.),
using a plus or a minus sign as an indication of whether or not a
particular government represents a given form of democracy.
[151] Here
Tocqueville gets it right: “The principle of equality may be
established in civil society without prevailing in the political
world.” (Tocqueville, vol. 2, 100).
[152]
Morris Berman makes a similar point (Berman, 296-297).
[153]
Danish philosopher Søren Kierkegaard (1813–1855) put it this way:
“The most dangerous revolutions are not those which tear everything
down, and cause the streets to run with blood, but those which leave
everything standing, while cunningly emptying it of any
significance.” Aldous
Huxley (1894–1963) said, in the Foreword to
Brave New World, “A really efficient totalitarian state would
be one in which the all-powerful executive of political bosses and
their army of managers control a population of slaves who do not
have to be coerced, because they love their servitude.”
[154] See
Richard Hofstadter, Anti-Intellectualism
in American Life.
[155] With
the installation of a strong central government—an oligarchy, under
the Constitution—American character and intellect declined. One has
only to dip into the writings of the Anti-Federalists to see the
difference. Almost immediately after the government shifted to
Washington, all discussion of government, its meaning and purpose,
its various forms and consequence, was replaced with the nasty
vindictiveness of the struggle for personal power.
[156] Says
the aristocratic Tocqueville, “I have often noticed in the United
States, that it is not easy to make a man understand that his
presence may be dispensed with; hints will not suffice to shake him
off. . . . This man will never understand that he wearies me to
death unless I tell him so, and the only way to get rid of him is to
make him my enemy for life.” (Tocqueville, vol. 2, 182)
[157]
Tocqueville was writing in the 1830s. How much more unhappy and
insecure is the American today? Consider how many millions are
taking some form of psychotropic medication, how many others abuse
alcohol and other drugs. Consider how many self-help books are sold
each year, as Americans continue their desperate search for
something that will make them feel better.
[158] “The
wise man,” writes Emerson, “is the state” (Emerson, Essays,
206).
[159] Here
is Tocqueville’s version: “In the United States a man builds a house
in which to spend his old age, and he sells it before the roof is
on; he plants a garden and lets it just as the trees are coming into
bearing; he brings a field into tillage and leaves other men to
gather the crops; he embraces a profession and gives it up; . . .
[he gets a few days vacation and he travels] fifteen hundred miles
in a few days to shake off his happiness . . . [in] his bootless
chase of that complete felicity which forever escapes him”
(Tocqueville, vol. 2, 144–145).
[160] “The oppressed,” says
Brazilian educator Paolo Freire, “are not only powerless, but
reconciled to their powerlessness, perceiving it fatalistically, as
a consequence of personal inadequacy or failure. The ultimate
product of highly unequal power relationships is a class unable to
articulate its own interests or perceive the existence of social
conflict.” Max Weber takes the argument a step further and actually
speaks of “the will to powerlessness.” Freire quoted in Roy Madron
and John Jopling, Gaian Democracies, 115; Weber,
Political Writings, p. 270.
[161] On
December 31, 2011, President Barack Obama signed the controversial
National Defense Authorization Act (NDAA) into law. The bill allows
the government to hand over suspected terrorists to the military for
indefinite detention—including U.S. citizens. Suspects are also
subjected to potentially being held on foreign soil in facilities
like Guantanamo Bay. People under scrutiny by the NDAA are tried
under a military tribunal instead of a judicial court, violating
their Fourth Amendment rights. In other words, what the Patriot Act
did for immigrants, the NDAA does for American citizens.
[162]
Walter A. McDougall, in Freedom Just Around the Corner: A New
American History, 1585–1828, has a different take. The American
is a con-man, he says. He makes his point with a lengthy discussion
of Herman Melville’s The Confidence-Man.
He then quotes from M. G. Jean de Crèvecoeur’s 1782 Letters from
an American Farmer. Americans, says Crèvecoeur, are “litigious,
overbearing, purse-proud,” their society “a general mass of keenness
and sagacious acting against another mass of equal sagacity. Happy
when it does not degenerate into fraud against fraud.” “Who is this
new man, this American?” asks McDougall. “As Melville would
certainly have it, he or she is a hustler” (McDougall, 4).
[163] Gore
Vidal has referred to Americans as “sheeple.”
[164] What
Mills neglects to mention is that the tawdry nature of electoral
campaigns was characteristic of national politics from the
beginning. The oligarchy created under the U.S. Constitution in 1787
spawned a vicious competition for personal power that has continued
unabated ever since. The Federalists and Alexander Hamilton were
spoken for by The Gazette of the United States. Thomas
Jefferson and the Republicans could count on Philip Freneau’s
The National Gazette. The virulence of the personal attacks
makes today’s campaigns seem gentlemanly by comparison.
[165] See
his Propaganda, 1928. Bernays’ point of view is discussed
in Chapter 2.
[166] Such
an outcome is consistent with what Wolin has called “inverted
totalitarianism,” a form of government whose genius “lies in
wielding total power without appearing to, without establishing
concentration camps, or enforcing ideological uniformity or forcibly
suppressing dissident elements so long as they remain ineffectual” (Wolin,
57) See the Introduction for a fuller discussion of Wolin’s ideas.
This essay is an extract from “Paradise Lost,
Paradise Regained: The True Meaning of Democracy,” by Arthur D.
Robbins, published by Acropolis Books. Learn more at acropolis-newyork.com
where you can find a complete bibliography of the works cited.