Why Can’t The World’s
Greatest Minds Solve The Mystery Of
Consciousness?
Philosophers and scientists have been at war
for decades over the question of what makes
human beings more than complex robots
By Oliver Burkeman
January
22, 2015 "ICH"
- "The
Guardian"
-
One
spring morning in Tucson, Arizona, in 1994,
an unknown philosopher named
David Chalmers got up to give a talk on
consciousness, by which he meant the
feeling of being inside your head, looking
out – or, to use the kind of language that
might give a neuroscientist an aneurysm, of
having a soul. Though he didn’t realise it
at the time, the young Australian academic
was about to ignite a war between
philosophers and scientists, by drawing
attention to a central mystery of human life
– perhaps the central mystery of
human life – and revealing how
embarrassingly far they were from solving
it.The scholars
gathered at the University of Arizona – for
what would later go down as a landmark
conference on the subject – knew they were
doing something edgy: in many quarters,
consciousness was still taboo, too weird and
new agey to take seriously, and some of the
scientists in the audience were risking
their reputations by attending. Yet the
first two talks that day, before Chalmers’s,
hadn’t proved thrilling. “Quite honestly,
they were totally unintelligible and boring
– I had no idea what anyone was talking
about,” recalled Stuart Hameroff, the
Arizona professor responsible for the event.
“As the organiser, I’m looking around, and
people are falling asleep, or getting
restless.” He grew worried. “But then the
third talk, right before the coffee break –
that was Dave.” With his long, straggly hair
and fondness for all-body denim, the
27-year-old Chalmers looked like he’d got
lost en route to a Metallica concert. “He
comes on stage, hair down to his butt, he’s
prancing around like Mick Jagger,” Hameroff
said. “But then he speaks. And that’s when
everyone wakes up.”
The brain, Chalmers began
by pointing out, poses all sorts of problems
to keep scientists busy. How do we learn,
store memories, or perceive things? How do
you know to jerk your hand away from
scalding water, or hear your name spoken
across the room at a noisy party? But these
were all “easy problems”, in the scheme of
things: given enough time and money, experts
would figure them out. There was only one
truly hard problem of consciousness,
Chalmers said. It was a puzzle so
bewildering that, in the months after his
talk, people started dignifying it with
capital letters – the Hard Problem of
Consciousness – and it’s this: why on
earth should all those complicated brain
processes feel like anything from
the inside? Why aren’t we just brilliant
robots, capable of retaining information, of
responding to noises and smells and hot
saucepans, but dark inside, lacking an inner
life? And how does the brain manage it? How
could the 1.4kg lump of moist, pinkish-beige
tissue inside your skull give rise to
something as mysterious as the experience of
being that pinkish-beige lump, and the
body to which it is attached?
What jolted Chalmers’s
audience from their torpor was how he had
framed the question. “At the coffee break, I
went around like a playwright on opening
night, eavesdropping,” Hameroff said. “And
everyone was like: ‘Oh! The Hard Problem!
The Hard Problem! That’s why we’re here!’”
Philosophers had pondered the so-called
“mind-body problem” for centuries. But
Chalmers’s particular manner of reviving it
“reached outside philosophy and galvanised
everyone. It defined the field. It made us
ask: what the hell is this that we’re
dealing with here?”
Two decades later, we know
an astonishing amount about the brain: you
can’t follow the news for a week without
encountering at least one more tale about
scientists discovering the brain region
associated with gambling, or laziness, or
love at first sight, or regret – and that’s
only the research that makes the headlines.
Meanwhile, the field of
artificial intelligence – which focuses
on recreating the abilities of the human
brain, rather than on what it feels like to
be one – has advanced stupendously. But like
an obnoxious relative who invites himself to
stay for a week and then won’t leave, the
Hard Problem remains. When I stubbed my toe
on the leg of the dining table this morning,
as any student of the brain could tell you,
nerve fibres called “C-fibres” shot a
message to my spinal cord, sending
neurotransmitters to the part of my brain
called the thalamus, which activated (among
other things) my limbic system. Fine. But
how come all that was accompanied by an
agonising flash of pain? And what is pain,
anyway?
Questions like these,
which straddle the border between science
and philosophy, make some experts openly
angry. They have caused others to argue that
conscious sensations, such as pain, don’t
really exist, no matter what I felt as I
hopped in anguish around the kitchen; or,
alternatively, that plants and trees must
also be conscious. The Hard Problem has
prompted arguments in serious journals about
what is going on in the mind of a zombie, or
– to quote the title of a famous 1974 paper
by the philosopher
Thomas Nagel – the question “What is it
like to be a bat?” Some argue that the
problem marks the boundary not just of what
we currently know, but of what science could
ever explain. On the other hand, in recent
years, a handful of neuroscientists have
come to believe that it may finally be about
to be solved – but only if we are willing to
accept the profoundly unsettling conclusion
that computers or the internet might soon
become conscious, too.
Next week, the conundrum
will move further into public awareness with
the opening of Tom Stoppard’s new play,
The Hard Problem, at the National
Theatre – the first play Stoppard has
written for the National since 2006, and the
last that the theatre’s head, Nicholas
Hytner, will direct before leaving his post
in March. The 77-year-old playwright has
revealed little about the play’s contents,
except that it concerns the question of
“what consciousness is and why it exists”,
considered from the perspective of a young
researcher played by Olivia Vinall. Speaking
to the Daily Mail, Stoppard also clarified a
potential misinterpretation of the title.
“It’s not about erectile dysfunction,” he
said.
Stoppard’s work has long
focused on grand, existential themes, so the
subject is fitting: when conversation turns
to the Hard Problem, even the most stubborn
rationalists lapse quickly into musings on
the meaning of life.
Christof Koch, the chief scientific
officer at the Allen Institute for Brain
Science, and a key player in the Obama
administration’s multibillion-dollar
initiative to map the human brain, is about
as credible as neuroscientists get. But, he
told me in December: “I think the earliest
desire that drove me to study consciousness
was that I wanted, secretly, to show myself
that it couldn’t be explained
scientifically. I was raised Roman Catholic,
and I wanted to find a place where I could
say: OK, here, God has intervened. God
created souls, and put them into people.”
Koch assured me that he had long ago
abandoned such improbable notions. Then, not
much later, and in all seriousness, he said
that on the basis of his recent research he
thought it wasn’t impossible that his iPhone
might have feelings.
By the time Chalmers
delivered his speech in Tucson, science had
been vigorously attempting to ignore the
problem of consciousness for a long time.
The source of the animosity dates back to
the 1600s, when René Descartes identified
the dilemma that would tie scholars in knots
for years to come. On the one hand,
Descartes realised, nothing is more obvious
and undeniable than the fact that you’re
conscious. In theory, everything else you
think you know about the world could be an
elaborate illusion cooked up to deceive you
– at this point, present-day writers
invariably invoke The Matrix – but your
consciousness itself can’t be illusory. On
the other hand, this most certain and
familiar of phenomena obeys none of the
usual rules of science. It doesn’t seem to
be physical. It can’t be observed, except
from within, by the conscious person. It
can’t even really be described. The mind,
Descartes concluded, must be made of some
special, immaterial stuff that didn’t abide
by the laws of nature; it had been
bequeathed to us by God.
This religious and rather
hand-wavy position, known as Cartesian
dualism, remained the governing assumption
into the 18th century and the early days of
modern brain study. But it was always bound
to grow unacceptable to an increasingly
secular scientific establishment that took
physicalism – the position that only
physical things exist – as its most basic
principle. And yet, even as neuroscience
gathered pace in the 20th century, no
convincing alternative explanation was
forthcoming. So little by little, the topic
became taboo. Few people doubted that the
brain and mind were very closely linked: if
you question this, try stabbing your brain
repeatedly with a kitchen knife, and see
what happens to your consciousness. But
how they were linked – or if they were
somehow exactly the same thing – seemed a
mystery best left to philosophers in their
armchairs. As late as 1989, writing in the
International Dictionary of Psychology, the
British psychologist
Stuart Sutherland could irascibly
declare of consciousness that “it is
impossible to specify what it is, what it
does, or why it evolved. Nothing worth
reading has been written on it.”
It was only in 1990 that
Francis Crick, the joint discoverer of
the double helix, used his position of
eminence to break ranks. Neuroscience was
far enough along by now, he declared in a
slightly tetchy paper co-written with
Christof Koch, that consciousness could no
longer be ignored. “It is remarkable,” they
began, “that most of the work in both
cognitive science and the neurosciences
makes no reference to consciousness” –
partly, they suspected, “because most
workers in these areas cannot see any useful
way of approaching the problem”. They
presented their own “sketch of a theory”,
arguing that certain neurons, firing at
certain frequencies, might somehow be the
cause of our inner awareness – though it was
not clear how.
“People thought I was
crazy to be getting involved,” Koch
recalled. “A senior colleague took me out to
lunch and said, yes, he had the utmost
respect for Francis, but Francis was a Nobel
laureate and a half-god and he could do
whatever he wanted, whereas I didn’t have
tenure yet, so I should be incredibly
careful. Stick to more mainstream science!
These fringey things – why not leave them
until retirement, when you’re coming close
to death, and you can worry about the soul
and stuff like that?”
As a child, Chalmers was
short-sighted in one eye, and he vividly
recalls the day he was first fitted with
glasses to rectify the problem. “Suddenly I
had proper binocular vision,” he said. “And
the world just popped out. It was
three-dimensional to me in a way it hadn’t
been.” He thought about that moment
frequently as he grew older. Of course, you
could tell a simple mechanical story about
what was going on in the lens of his
glasses, his eyeball, his retina, and his
brain. “But how does that explain the way
the world just pops out like that?” To a
physicalist, the glasses-eyeball-retina
story is the only story. But to a
thinker of Chalmers’s persuasion, it was
clear that it wasn’t enough: it told you
what the machinery of the eye was doing, but
it didn’t begin to explain that sudden,
breathtaking experience of depth and
clarity. Chalmers’s “zombie” thought
experiment is his attempt to show why the
mechanical account is not enough – why the
mystery of conscious awareness goes deeper
than a purely material science can explain.
“Look, I’m not a zombie,
and I pray that you’re not a zombie,”
Chalmers said, one Sunday before Christmas,
“but the point is that evolution could
have produced zombies instead of conscious
creatures – and it didn’t!” We were drinking
espressos in his faculty apartment at New
York University, where he recently took up a
full-time post at what is widely considered
the leading philosophy department in the
Anglophone world; boxes of his belongings,
shipped over from Australia, lay unpacked
around his living-room. Chalmers, now 48,
recently cut his hair in a concession to
academic respectability, and he wears less
denim, but his ideas remain as heavy-metal
as ever. The zombie scenario goes as
follows: imagine that you have a
doppelgänger. This person physically
resembles you in every respect, and behaves
identically to you; he or she holds
conversations, eats and sleeps, looks happy
or anxious precisely as you do. The sole
difference is that the doppelgänger has no
consciousness; this – as opposed to a
groaning, blood-spattered walking corpse
from a movie – is what philosophers mean by
a “zombie”.
Such non-conscious
humanoids don’t exist, of course. (Or
perhaps it would be better to say that I
know I’m not one, anyhow; I could never know
for certain that you aren’t.) But the point
is that, in principle, it feels as if they
could. Evolution might have
produced creatures that were atom-for-atom
the same as humans, capable of everything
humans can do, except with no spark of
awareness inside. As Chalmers explained:
“I’m talking to you now, and I can see how
you’re behaving; I could do a brain scan,
and find out exactly what’s going on in your
brain – yet it seems it could be consistent
with all that evidence that you have no
consciousness at all.” If you were
approached by me and my doppelgänger, not
knowing which was which, not even the most
powerful brain scanner in existence could
tell us apart. And the fact that one can
even imagine this scenario is sufficient to
show that consciousness can’t just be made
of ordinary physical atoms. So consciousness
must, somehow, be something extra – an
additional ingredient in nature.
It would be understating
things a bit to say that this argument
wasn’t universally well-received when
Chalmers began to advance it, most
prominently in his 1996 book
The Conscious Mind. The withering tone
of the philosopher Massimo Pigliucci sums up
the thousands of words that have been
written attacking the zombie notion: “Let’s
relegate zombies to B-movies and try to be a
little more serious about our philosophy,
shall we?” Yes, it may be true that most of
us, in our daily lives, think of
consciousness as something over and above
our physical being – as if your mind were “a
chauffeur inside your own body”, to quote
the spiritual author Alan Watts. But to
accept this as a scientific principle would
mean rewriting the laws of physics.
Everything we know about the universe tells
us that reality consists only of physical
things: atoms and their component particles,
busily colliding and combining. Above all,
critics point out, if this non-physical
mental stuff did exist, how could it cause
physical things to happen – as when the
feeling of pain causes me to jerk my fingers
away from the saucepan’s edge?
Nonetheless, just
occasionally, science has dropped
tantalising hints that this spooky extra
ingredient might be real. In the 1970s, at
what was then the National Hospital for
Nervous Diseases in London, the neurologist
Lawrence Weiskrantz encountered a patient,
known as “DB”, with a blind spot in his left
visual field, caused by brain damage.
Weiskrantz showed him patterns of striped
lines, positioned so that they fell on his
area of blindness, then asked him to say
whether the stripes were vertical or
horizontal. Naturally, DB protested that he
could see no stripes at all. But Weiskrantz
insisted that he guess the answers anyway –
and DB got them right almost 90% of the
time. Apparently, his brain was perceiving
the stripes without his mind being conscious
of them. One interpretation is that DB was a
semi-zombie, with a brain like any other
brain, but partially lacking the magical
add-on of consciousness.
Chalmers knows how wildly
improbable his ideas can seem, and takes
this in his stride: at philosophy
conferences, he is fond of clambering on
stage to sing The Zombie Blues, a lament
about the miseries of having no
consciousness. (“I act like you act / I do
what you do / But I don’t know / What it’s
like to be you.”) “The conceit is: wouldn’t
it be a drag to be a zombie? Consciousness
is what makes life worth living, and I don’t
even have that: I’ve got the zombie blues.”
The song has improved since its debut more
than a decade ago, when he used to try to
hold a tune. “Now I’ve realised it sounds
better if you just shout,” he said.
The consciousness debates
have provoked more mudslinging and fury than
most in modern philosophy, perhaps because
of how baffling the problem is: opposing
combatants tend not merely to disagree, but
to find each other’s positions manifestly
preposterous. An admittedly extreme example
concerns the Canadian-born philosopher Ted
Honderich, whose book On Consciousness was
described,
in an article by his fellow philosopher
Colin McGinn in 2007, as “banal and
pointless”, “excruciating”, “absurd”,
running “the full gamut from the mediocre to
the ludicrous to the merely bad”. McGinn
added, in a footnote: “The review that
appears here is not as I originally wrote
it. The editors asked me to ‘soften the
tone’ of the original [and] I have done so.”
(The attack may have been partly motivated
by a passage in Honderich’s autobiography,
in which he mentions “my small colleague
Colin McGinn”; at the time, Honderich told
this newspaper he’d enraged McGinn by
referring to a girlfriend of his as “not as
plain as the old one”.)
McGinn, to be fair, has
made a career from such hatchet jobs. But
strong feelings only slightly more politely
expressed are commonplace. Not everybody
agrees there is a Hard Problem to begin with
– making the whole debate kickstarted by
Chalmers an exercise in pointlessness.
Daniel Dennett, the high-profile atheist
and professor at Tufts University outside
Boston, argues that consciousness, as we
think of it, is an illusion: there just
isn’t anything in addition to the spongy
stuff of the brain, and that spongy stuff
doesn’t actually give rise to something
called consciousness. Common sense may tell
us there’s a subjective world of inner
experience – but then common sense told us
that the sun orbits the Earth, and that the
world was flat. Consciousness, according to
Dennett’s theory, is like a conjuring trick:
the normal functioning of the brain just
makes it look as if there is something
non-physical going on. To look for a real,
substantive thing called consciousness,
Dennett argues, is as silly as insisting
that characters in novels, such as Sherlock
Holmes or Harry Potter, must be made up of a
peculiar substance named “fictoplasm”; the
idea is absurd and unnecessary, since the
characters do not exist to begin with. This
is the point at which the debate tends to
collapse into incredulous laughter and
head-shaking: neither camp can quite believe
what the other is saying. To Dennett’s
opponents, he is simply denying the
existence of something everyone knows for
certain: their inner experience of sights,
smells, emotions and the rest. (Chalmers has
speculated, largely in jest, that Dennett
himself might be a zombie.) It’s like
asserting that cancer doesn’t exist, then
claiming you’ve cured cancer; more than one
critic of Dennett’s most famous book,
Consciousness Explained, has joked that its
title ought to be Consciousness Explained
Away. Dennett’s reply is characteristically
breezy: explaining things away, he insists,
is exactly what scientists do. When
physicists first concluded that the only
difference between gold and silver was the
number of subatomic particles in their
atoms, he writes, people could have felt
cheated, complaining that their special
“goldness” and “silveriness” had been
explained away. But everybody now accepts
that goldness and silveriness are really
just differences in atoms. However hard it
feels to accept, we should concede that
consciousness is just the physical brain,
doing what brains do.
“The history of science is
full of cases where people thought a
phenomenon was utterly unique, that
there couldn’t be any possible
mechanism for it, that we might never
solve it, that there was nothing in
the universe like it,” said Patricia
Churchland of the University of California,
a self-described “neurophilosopher” and one
of Chalmers’s most forthright critics.
Churchland’s opinion of the Hard Problem,
which she expresses in caustic vocal
italics, is that it is nonsense, kept alive
by philosophers who fear that science might
be about to eliminate one of the puzzles
that has kept them gainfully employed for
years. Look at the precedents: in the 17th
century, scholars were convinced that light
couldn’t possibly be physical – that it had
to be something occult, beyond the usual
laws of nature. Or take life itself: early
scientists were convinced that there had to
be some magical spirit – the élan vital
– that distinguished living beings from mere
machines. But there wasn’t, of course. Light
is electromagnetic radiation; life is just
the label we give to certain kinds of
objects that can grow and reproduce.
Eventually, neuroscience will show that
consciousness is just brain states.
Churchland said: “The history of science
really gives you perspective on how easy it
is to talk ourselves into this sort of
thinking – that if my big, wonderful brain
can’t envisage the solution, then it must be
a really, really hard problem!”
Solutions have regularly
been floated: the literature is awash in
references to “global workspace theory”,
“ego tunnels”, “microtubules”, and
speculation that quantum theory may provide
a way forward. But the intractability of the
arguments has caused some thinkers, such as
Colin McGinn, to raise an intriguing if
ultimately defeatist possibility: what if
we’re just constitutionally incapable of
ever solving the Hard Problem? After all,
our brains evolved to help us solve
down-to-earth problems of survival and
reproduction; there is no particular reason
to assume they should be capable of cracking
every big philosophical puzzle we happen to
throw at them. This stance has become known
as “mysterianism” – after the 1960s Michigan
rock’n’roll band ? and the Mysterians, who
themselves borrowed the name from a work of
Japanese sci-fi – but the essence of it is
that there’s actually no mystery to why
consciousness hasn’t been explained: it’s
that humans aren’t up to the job. If we
struggle to understand what it could
possibly mean for the mind to be physical,
maybe that’s because we are, to quote the
American philosopher Josh Weisberg, in the
position of “squirrels trying to understand
quantum mechanics”. In other words: “It’s
just not going to happen.”
* * *
Or maybe it is: in the
last few years, several scientists and
philosophers, Chalmers and Koch among them,
have begun to look seriously again at a
viewpoint so bizarre that it has been
neglected for more than a century, except
among followers of eastern spiritual
traditions, or in the kookier corners of the
new age. This is “panpsychism”, the dizzying
notion that everything in the universe might
be conscious, or at least potentially
conscious, or conscious when put into
certain configurations. Koch concedes that
this sounds ridiculous: when he mentions
panpsychism, he has written, “I often
encounter blank stares of incomprehension.”
But when it comes to grappling with the Hard
Problem, crazy-sounding theories are an
occupational hazard. Besides, panpsychism
might help unravel an enigma that has
attached to the study of consciousness from
the start: if humans have it, and apes have
it, and dogs and pigs probably have it, and
maybe birds, too – well, where does it stop?
Growing up as the child of
German-born Catholics, Koch had a dachshund
named Purzel. According to the church,
because he was a dog, that meant he didn’t
have a soul. But he whined when anxious and
yelped when injured – “he certainly gave
every appearance of having a rich inner
life”. These days we don’t much speak of
souls, but it is widely assumed that many
non-human brains are conscious – that a dog
really does feel pain when he is hurt. The
problem is that there seems to be no logical
reason to draw the line at dogs, or sparrows
or mice or insects, or, for that matter,
trees or rocks. Since we don’t know how the
brains of mammals create consciousness, we
have no grounds for assuming it’s only the
brains of mammals that do so – or even that
consciousness requires a brain at all. Which
is how Koch and Chalmers have both found
themselves arguing, in the pages of the New
York Review of Books, that an ordinary
household thermostat or a photodiode, of the
kind you might find in your smoke detector,
might in principle be conscious.
The argument unfolds as
follows: physicists have no problem
accepting that certain fundamental aspects
of reality – such as space, mass, or
electrical charge – just do exist. They
can’t be explained as being the result of
anything else. Explanations have to stop
somewhere. The panpsychist hunch is that
consciousness could be like that, too – and
that if it is, there is no particular reason
to assume that it only occurs in certain
kinds of matter.
Koch’s specific twist on
this idea, developed with the neuroscientist
and psychiatrist Giulio Tononi, is narrower
and more precise than traditional
panpsychism. It is the argument that
anything at all could be conscious,
providing that the information it contains
is sufficiently interconnected and organised.
The human brain certainly fits the bill; so
do the brains of cats and dogs, though their
consciousness probably doesn’t resemble
ours. But in principle the same might apply
to the internet, or a smartphone, or a
thermostat. (The ethical implications are
unsettling: might we owe the same care to
conscious machines that we bestow on
animals? Koch, for his part, tries to avoid
stepping on insects as he walks.)
Unlike the vast majority
of musings on the Hard Problem, moreover,
Tononi and Koch’s “integrated information
theory” has actually been tested. A team of
researchers led by Tononi has designed a
device that stimulates the brain with
electrical voltage, to measure how
interconnected and organised – how
“integrated” – its neural circuits are. Sure
enough, when people fall into a deep sleep,
or receive an injection of anaesthetic, as
they slip into unconsciousness, the device
demonstrates that their brain integration
declines, too. Among patients suffering
“locked-in syndrome” – who are as conscious
as the rest of us – levels of brain
integration remain high; among patients in
coma – who aren’t – it doesn’t. Gather
enough of this kind of evidence, Koch argues
and in theory you could take any device,
measure the complexity of the information
contained in it, then deduce whether or not
it was conscious.
But even if one were
willing to accept the perplexing claim that
a smartphone could be conscious, could you
ever know that it was true? Surely only the
smartphone itself could ever know that? Koch
shrugged. “It’s like black holes,” he said.
“I’ve never been in a black hole.
Personally, I have no experience of black
holes. But the theory [that predicts black
holes] seems always to be true, so I tend to
accept it.”
It would be satisfying for
multiple reasons if a theory like this were
eventually to vanquish the Hard Problem. On
the one hand, it wouldn’t require a belief
in spooky mind-substances that reside inside
brains; the laws of physics would escape
largely unscathed. On the other hand, we
wouldn’t need to accept the strange and
soulless claim that consciousness doesn’t
exist, when it’s so obvious that it does. On
the contrary, panpsychism says, it’s
everywhere. The universe is throbbing with
it.
Last June, several of the
most prominent combatants in the
consciousness debates – including Chalmers,
Churchland and Dennett – boarded a tall-masted
yacht for a trip among the ice floes of
Greenland. This conference-at-sea was funded
by a Russian internet entrepreneur, Dmitry
Volkov, the founder of the Moscow Centre for
Consciousness Studies. About 30 academics
and graduate students, plus crew, spent a
week gliding through dark waters, past
looming snow-topped mountains and glaciers,
in a bracing chill conducive to focused
thought, giving the problem of consciousness
another shot. In the mornings, they visited
islands to go hiking, or examine the ruins
of ancient stone huts; in the afternoons,
they held conference sessions on the boat.
For Chalmers, the setting only sharpened the
urgency of the mystery: how could you feel
the Arctic wind on your face, take in the
visual sweep of vivid greys and whites and
greens, and still claim conscious experience
was unreal, or that it was simply the result
of ordinary physical stuff, behaving
ordinarily?
The question was
rhetorical. Dennett and Churchland were not
converted; indeed, Chalmers has no
particular confidence that a consensus will
emerge in the next century. “Maybe there’ll
be some amazing new development that leaves
us all, now, looking like pre-Darwinians
arguing about biology,” he said. “But it
wouldn’t surprise me in the least if in 100
years, neuroscience is incredibly
sophisticated, if we have a complete map of
the brain – and yet some people are still
saying, ‘Yes, but how does any of that give
you consciousness?’ while others are saying
‘No, no, no – that just is the
consciousness!’” The Greenland cruise
concluded in collegial spirits, and mutual
incomprehension.
It would be poetic –
albeit deeply frustrating – were it
ultimately to prove that the one thing the
human mind is incapable of comprehending is
itself. An answer must be out there
somewhere. And finding it matters: indeed,
one could argue that nothing else could ever
matter more – since anything at all that
matters, in life, only does so as a
consequence of its impact on conscious
brains. Yet there’s no reason to assume that
our brains will be adequate vessels for the
voyage towards that answer. Nor that, were
we to stumble on a solution to the Hard
Problem, on some distant shore where
neuroscience meets philosophy, we would even
recognise that we’d found it.
Follow the Long Read
on Twitter:
@gdnlongread